↑ Provided by Norman E. Hooben ↑ |
Realism and Islam
Our leaders cannot comprehend what is
going on, either when a whole Western civilization
loses its faith and moral
standards or when Islam reawakens to the implications of its own faith and its
vision of world conquest.
Political realism, long associated with Augustine, constrains us to consider what Machiavelli later recommended to us—namely, to look at what men “do” do and not at what they “ought” to do. This advice would be more persuasive if, in fact, some men did not do what they ought to do or others do what they ought not to do. Both sides usually persuade themselves that they ought to follow their convictions. Machiavelli thought that if men did what they “ought” to do they would not survive the onslaughts and cunning of those who did what they had power to do whatever they could do. However, Augustinian realism did not, as in the case of Machiavelli, justify this careful look at what men “do” do as a reason to deny the distinction between good and evil so that any means could be used to accomplish their purposes.
Political realism, long associated with Augustine, constrains us to consider what Machiavelli later recommended to us—namely, to look at what men “do” do and not at what they “ought” to do. This advice would be more persuasive if, in fact, some men did not do what they ought to do or others do what they ought not to do. Both sides usually persuade themselves that they ought to follow their convictions. Machiavelli thought that if men did what they “ought” to do they would not survive the onslaughts and cunning of those who did what they had power to do whatever they could do. However, Augustinian realism did not, as in the case of Machiavelli, justify this careful look at what men “do” do as a reason to deny the distinction between good and evil so that any means could be used to accomplish their purposes.
The “realistic” look was “realistic” for
Augustine precisely because good and evil were included in the look itself,
in the reality as seen. To see and act on the reality of good or evil is to see
reality in its fullest dimensions. Practical truth, in terms of acting
according to an accurate description of what is there, is the first principle
of realism as well as of political action. Thus, Maritain could rightly
maintain in the Augustinian tradition that “justice, brains, and strength” need
not be separated. They belong together. Or, to refer obliquely to Lord Acton,
the lack of power can also corrupt absolutely. Not to possess and use
responsible power in defense of what is right is itself an evil, cowardice.
With this background in mind, we recall recent
events from “9/11”, the bombings in Spain, England, Mumbai, Bali, Fort Hood,
San Bernardino, twice in Paris, Lahore, and Brussels, not to mention the
persecutions and beheadings in Pakistan, Iraq, Yemen, Nigeria, Libya, Somalia,
Chad, Syria, and the Sunni/Shiite inner-Muslim battles. What is the most
plausible way to judge such continuing violence and its origins? To make this
assessment, we have to acknowledge that Islam, in principle, is actually and
potentially violent throughout its entire history. The basic reason for this
method is obedience to the Law of Allah, not love for violence itself.
On the basis of evidence and theory, we cannot
conclude from the fact that Islam is a “religion” that therefore it is not
“violent” or is so only by abuse of its own founding. It is possible to be a
religion and to espouse violence. (Were this not so, we would have to exclude
many key passages on the Old Testament itself.) We cannot obscure what is there
and affirmed to be there by Muslims themselves. Realism means that we can and
should call what happens by its proper name. It also means that, if we cannot
or will not make this proper naming, we are not realistic. We will inevitably
suffer the consequences of our failure to state the truth of what is there.
These things are said not to promote counter
violence against Muslims or to justify Muslim violence against others. Rather
it is to respect Islam’s insistence that all those inside and outside of its
enclosure be subject to the law of the Prophet. Whether we like it or not, this
vision of world rule that is proper to Islam can only be called “religious” in
nature. It is rooted in and promoted as a worship of the god called Allah. Not
to take this wording seriously is unrealistic. The Muslims who claim that they
can read their religious texts as if such violence is not advocated and
justified may be applauded for trying to mitigate the historic record. But the
fact is that those who see this violence as essential to the religion have the
better side of the argument and are the better witnesses to what historic Islam
stands for.
II.
What is argued here, then, is not to be
unfairly “critical” of Islam. On the contrary, it is written with considerable
admiration for the zeal, consistency, and effectiveness displayed over the
centuries by Islamic armies and law. And while it may be politically incorrect
to state these things, they need to be stated and are in fact the truth—things
that both Muslims and non-Muslims need to hear and consider. The designated and
determined goal of the conquest of the world for Allah has been reinvigorated
again and again in world history from the time of Mohammed in the seventh
century. These revivals and expansions, which have only been temporarily halted
by superior counterforce, have roots in the Qur’an itself and in its
commentaries.
What we witness today, much to our surprise, is
but another step in the historic world mission that Islam envisions for itself
as the will of Allah, a goal that inspires the real and recurrent vigor that is
found in its history. The reason we do not call it what it is lies not in Islam
but in our own very different concepts of philosophy, religion, and law. In
this sense, it is our own culture that often prevents us from being ourselves
political realists.
Many believing Muslims, likely more than we are
willing to admit, are tired and frustrated at having their religion’s
principles denied. Outside observers are unwilling to believe or imagine that
what Muslim advocates say about themselves, both in their founding texts and in
their historic actions, is true. World conquest over time is what they hold
must be achieved.
In other words, whether they be Muslim or
otherwise, many people refuse to acknowledge that violence is proposed and
carried out in the name of Islam. Outside Islam, it is called by the peculiar
word “terrorism”. It is rarely called what it is, namely, a religious endeavor
to conquer the world as an act of piety. Muslims, in this central tradition,
are not “terrorists” just for the fun of it. That is insulting and resented.
They practice what we call “terror” because they see themselves carrying out
the will of Allah, even sometimes to their own death in doing so. Those who, in
the process, kill “infidels”—that is, any non-Muslim or Muslim who does not
accept true Islam—is considered to be a “martyr” to the cause of Islam. Only if
Islam is not true can these ritual killings be seen as the objective evil that
they are.
A subtle philosophic theory (called “voluntarism”)
purports to justify this usage of what we call terror for religious purposes.
The principle of contradiction cannot hold in a “revelation” that contains, in
its texts, contradictory commands, as does the Qur’an. Allah then must become
pure will, not bound by Logos or reason. Hence Allah is not
limited by any distinction of good and evil. The Muslim blasphemy laws that
threaten with death anyone who violates this claim arise from this source.
Allah’s mandate to Islam is progressively to
subject the world to his will and to the law based on it. Terror will end and
true “peace” will result only when all are submissive to Allah and live under
Muslim law in all its details. What we outside of Islam call acts of violence
are considered within it to be the carrying out of Allah’s will. Gruesome
beheadings of Christians, however innocent, are seen as acts of justice. They
are acts of “virtue” in this sense. The people who cannot understand this
religious charge given to Islam, whether they be themselves Muslim or not, are
themselves both unrealistic and dangerous. Their own presuppositions prevent
them from recognizing and judging the real issue. They also prevents them from
doing anything effective to hinder this expansion of Islam into Europe, Asia,
Africa, and America.
III.
Back in 1975, I wrote an essay in the Modern Age
entitled “On
the Teaching of Ancient and Medieval Political Theory”. The gist of this
essay was that unless we understand the content and history of religions—their
truth claims and aberrations—we will be unable to see the actual forces that
swirl through the political world. An education that lacks a proper and
accurate study of the theology and theologies peculiar to each different
religion is not really an education. It could not prepare anyone to deal with a
world in which religions, in their differences, are a reality. Both in Europe
and America in the last half century or longer, this sanitized education is what
decades of students have been given. With it, most citizens are simply not
equipped to face the forces now reappearing in the world. Indeed, even to
propose a realistic look at Islam, as is proposed here, is almost everywhere
forbidden and excluded from any consideration, however valid the analysis.
This neglect of or hostility to religion has
come back to haunt us. We have lumped all “religions” together as illusions or
myths. They are to be defanged and wholly subject to state power. Our
political, academic, and cultural leaders cannot comprehend what is going on,
either when a whole Western civilization loses its faith and moral standards or
when Islam reawakens to the implications of its own faith and its vision of
world conquest. The two—the loss of faith and the rise of Islam—are connected.
The decline of the birth rate and civil undermining of the family in the West
is one thing. Muslim immigration or invasion has engulfed this same area.
Muslims, especially young males, did not seek power and prosperity in other
adjoining Muslim lands. The expansion of Islam was justified also by its charge
of moral decadence against the West.
We see well-equipped modern armies, with inept
and not seeing political leadership and with little motivation of forces,
out-fought by young armed zealots in pick-up trucks who can, with their
followers, threaten every train station and public building in Europe, Africa,
Asia, and America. As they planned, they have managed to turn the whole world
into a battleground of fear. The cry “Allah be praised!” is heard after every
act of destruction. It is quite clear by now, or should be, that no cultural
artifacts—be they books, buildings, statues, or paintings—will be allowed to exist.
They are seen to be contrary to Allah’s will, no matter what they are or when
created. In this sense, the Pyramids, the Buddhist statues, the library in
Timbuktu, the Vatican, and the monasteries in the deserts, Canterbury, the
towers in New York, the kosher markets in Paris, and the airports in Brussels
are equally subject to destruction. Everything must be protected because
everything is now threatened.
Not only are individual Christians eradicated
but so are the statues of their saints. The reason for this destruction is
“religious”. Such things ought not to exist. We have here a literal application
of the belief that nothing should be allowed public or private space that does
not correspond with strict Muslim beliefs. Provisional tolerance of Christians
and Jews if they accept second class citizenship and pay heavy fines is merely
temporary until the conquest is complete. Such zealous destruction to do the
will of Allah, in other words, is considered to be an act of piety. If someone
is going to oppose such acts, it cannot be done on the grounds of opposition to
“terror” or that it is unreasonable. Ultimately, it depends, as Augustine
learned with the Donatists, on a conversion and rejection of the theology that
justifies it.
IV.
Whether Islam, in its origins, is a rereading
of Jewish, Nestorian, and Christian texts (as it probably is) can be disputed.
First, Islam claims to be a literal revelation of what is in the mind or being
of Allah. In this sense, what is in the text must always remain in the text. It
cannot be changed or “reinterpreted” to leave out those multiple passages that
propose and justify violence in the name of the expansion of this religion.
This advocacy of violence, which has been practiced in Islam from its seventh
century beginning, has a purpose. This purpose is, ultimately, religious and
pious. Whether the Muslim notion of “heaven,” where its martyrs go, is
primarily this-worldly or transcendent, can also be disputed. In any case, the
concept of heaven is very earthy sounding. This picture is not, as such, an
argument against its truth.
The message contained in the Qur’an is that the
world should bow in submissive worship to Allah. This purpose abides and recurs
over the centuries because it is there in the text. Men may temporarily neglect
its zealous pursuit, but the text itself always contains the mission for others
to find and pursue. There will always be those who realize that the mission of
world conquest in the name of Allah is not complete. This realization is why,
so long as it exists unrefuted, the Qur’an will always produce what we call
“terrorists”. What we see now is little different from what has been seen
throughout the centuries wherever Islam is found.
In this view, the world is divided into an area
of peace and an area of war. The former is where the law of Allah rules
politically, religiously, and culturally, where no other philosophy or faith
has any right to be present. All signs of alien religion, art, artifact, and
people are eliminated through forced conversion or death. Sometimes, Christians
and Jews can be allowed to stay alive provided that they accept second class
citizenship and pay taxes. This situation, in practice, is the basic
constitutional rule in all existing Muslim states, even in those that reject
ISIS or other approaches to eventual conquest of the world. Once Islam has
conquered, it has always followed the same principles. In its history, certain
famous battles have turned back Muslim conquests for a time, sometimes for
centuries. But this relative inertness is only on the surface. As long as the
book exists, its goals will again and again inflame prophets, imams,
politicians, and the young men to recommence the conquest of the rest of the
world.
In conclusion, what is argued here in terms of
political realism is that we must understand the religious nature of Islamic
expansion and the methods used to achieve it. By trying to abstract these
motivation from the soul of this particular religion, which is, on this score,
unlike most others, only makes it impossible to describe what in fact is going
on in the mind of the adversary that is Islam. Wars are first fought in
minds—and this is a war. It is not World War III; rather, it is an extension of
the wars that Mohammed first launched against Byzantium, Persia, Syria,
eventually North Africa, even to India, Spain, the and Balkans.
The Muslim protagonists of today realize how
close they were several times in the past to conquering Europe as the next step
in world conquest. What they see today is a very realistic opportunity to
succeed where their ancestors failed. They, though also idealists, are (often
unlike ourselves) realists. That is, they see what our minds really hold. And
they see that they are largely empty of what really counts in this world: a
true conception of God. Their only fault is that of choosing a false
understanding of the real God. Aside from this “small” issue, one cannot help
but admire, and fear, a blind faith that so abides over time and place without
the real presence of the Logos whose incarnate presence in
the world is explicitly denied.